A
controversy has been raised again that Girard’s self-designated anthropology is
a system of thought not deserving that appellation. As if to corroborate
this claim it has been pointed out that it has not made as much as a mark in the field of
anthropology proper.
Not being an anthropologist myself, I would nevertheless easily
concede that Girard’s thought does not amount to a well-rounded anthropology. Yet
I admire many of his insights and think that they have “changed my life,” but
more for religious reasons than any others. Of course, his theory has many
facets, and the basic mimetic aspect of it is in my opinion not only illuminating,
nay, ground-breaking but also unimpeachable. But when this mimesis escalates to
extremes, when scapegoats are created and condemned to ostensibly produce the “sacred”
– that is, where the whole theory bears on anthropology the most – I do
have my doubts. The main reason being that it is difficult if not impossible to
find examples of this mechanism outside mythic settings in order to be able to establish
how universal the scenario of an innocent scapegoat being declared guilty then
becoming “sacred,” with peace ensuing, actually is. The most doubtful to me is
the purported prevalence of the last step. The fact that, as Girard declared, the
mechanism ceased operating following the Christian revelation does not help either.
No production of the peace-bestowing sacred any more, while scapegoats’ supply seemingly
remains undiminished, though they are now a different breed, many of them
self-designated.
I do not have any doubts in the case of Jesus as seen
through the Girardian lens, though. That particular case, as standing in total
contradistinction to the regular resolution of scapegoating AS POSITED by
Girard, gives an incredible intellectual as well as moral boost and guidance to
the Christian. It has the potential to transform those who come under its (or
rather His, the innocent self-sacrificing victim’s) spell.
But the scapegoating scenario as such in Girard’s thought
emerges from his reading of myth and various scriptures, and is descried by him
in “secular” literature as well, as the completion of the mimetic cycle. Now obviously
Girard could have only read so much, and picked this piece of literature as
opposed to that. And his choices are telling as well as being reflected in his
theory.
One important choice or rather omission is his dismissal
of Buddhism – with its take on and proposed solution to the MIMETIC CYCLE. I
put it in capital letters to underscore that classical Buddhism, in its
voluminous literature, scriptural and otherwise, actually saw and dealt with
the very problem that was of preeminent interest for Girard. Yet he chose to
disregard it, even though at the end of his life he investigated sacrifice in
Hinduism, and Buddhism obviously had been an anti-sacrificial response to that
religion or rather slew of religions. For an anthropology staking its claim to
importance based on the role of sacrifice it should certainly be worthwhile to investigate
Buddhism both in terms of its religious content, as well as its societal and cultural
expressions. It becomes even more indicated if one bears in mind that many
Buddhists have been claiming all along that their religion is actually a
psychology.
Buddhism’s main preoccupation is actually with mimesis of
desire, it could be construed as largely a psychology of defusing the mimetic
cycle. How could then have it been ignored by Girard? Was he, as he has been
charged, myopic in seeing only things Western as worth investigating? Or was it
that he did not like the proposed solutions? I am convinced that it is the latter. Actually he did say
precisely that stating that Buddhism amounted to nihilism. Still it is a great
pity that it must have been that he chose to ignore it rather than investigate.
What follows is an outline of Buddhism as religion/psychology
seen through the lens of those above-mentioned preeminent Girardian topics. Then
I move on to a very brief outline of Buddhist history and culture to ground
that religion-psychology in context, also worthy of anthropological inquiry.
Buddhism’s solution to the heart-rending mimesis of
desire, which is fully acknowledged there as the most disruptive human quality,
is not transcendental (or innermost) mimesis of Christ – as Girard came to
propose, which insight is obviously rejected by non-Christian Girardian (they
of course have the right to do so, the thought is able to stand its ground even
absent this insight) – but by pointing to the possibility of doing away with
mimesis altogether. That Girard would not acknowledge – or even investigate.
Now how man can escape this seemingly ineluctable
predicament of imitating someone else’s desire, escalating in due course, and
through well defined, inevitable stages,
to a crisis that might end up in violence? According to Buddhism two
initial insights are crucial: (1) desire always produces suffering, (2) to
avoid this suffering one has to realize that – as everything is impermanent,
including man himself, and one’s suffering and the desire that caused it in the
first place – one does not really, or
substantially, exist.
But that is only a concept and as such cannot possibly be
meaningful to a desire-ridden man. How can it become relevant to man? Through a
process of gaining experiential knowledge of it. How is it accomplished?
Through a thorough grounding in insight meditation.
Many religion experts will admit that initial beliefs
largely determine what is later confirmed by religious practices, including
such as meditation/contemplation. And so it is with Buddhist practice. People
are initially drawn to its tenets wanting to solve their life problems, and are
able to come out of practice with stronger, experiential grounding in them. The
same is true of Christianity or any other religion, unless something out of the
ordinary happens to shake the initial belief system. Or, especially these days,
getting weary not seeing the DESIRED results fast enough, they find something
seemingly more attractive in the spiritual marketplace.
I think that the differing perceptions of suffering are
crucial in a comparative analysis of the two religions. Christianity is
sometimes in a caricature fashion portrayed as extolling suffering. Normally
suffering is considered there as being part and parcel of human life and as
such should not be avoided at all cost. But that is precisely what classical Buddhism
is advocating. Moreover, and more important as well, it sees this task as
feasible.
Remember now the two approaches: classical Buddhism –
doing away with desire (and thus also with mimesis of desire); Christianity
(according to Girard, but also to many saints and mystics; vide Thomas a
Kempis’ Imitatio Christi) – positive, or transcendental (or innermost)
mimesis of Christ; the latter seemingly replete with unavoidable suffering.
But why the latter would have to be so? Because man
falters along the way? Yes, but preeminently because he is delusional about
himself, not (immediately) seeing that instead of following Christ he is
actually puffing up his self or ego. This “exalted” self is of course taken to
be false, but that is a weak consolation to a faltering man, charged with the
task of constant spiritual discernment if he is to have any chance of
salvation. Man is in a double bind:
desire as such has its own dynamic where it easily loses its initial goal of
imitating Christ, and gets diverted to competing with and envying fellow men
pursuing the same goal – if not to other, overtly sinful, pursuits.
Can man, as classical Buddhism posits, do entirely away
with desire, as opposed to appetite, and thus also with mimesis, if we assume
Girard’s view of desire being entirely mimetic? Even only if and when eagerly
pursuing meditative practices ostensibly designed to accomplish that? Let us
see what state-of-the-art neuroscience has to say on that.
Obviously no neuroscientific study has addressed precisely
this problem. Yet many studies have tangentially touched upon it, to the extent
that it is at least possible to somehow reflect on, rather than fully
investigate, the subject.
What needs to be addressed first of all is whether the
concept of mimesis can be construed as bearing only on desire. On the one hand,
that is where Girard’s thought seems to limit itself. On the other,
neuroscience posits that mirror neurons, which are operational if not
indispensable in any mimesis, are also involved in the mechanism of empathy.
And that is where Buddhism seems to have been compelled to step back from
positing a fully quality-less self, that is no-self, as man’s proximate goal striven
for in meditation – by exhorting him to cultivate empathy-based loving-kindness
in that same meditation where one is supposed to be gaining insight into one’s
impermanent, immaterial “no-self.”
How can this be made consistent? Is there practically possible
a “pure,” essentially atomistic, Buddhist approach? Certainly neuroscience
might be of help, allowing any concept of “self” to be fleshed out if not
corroborated or refuted. What immediately becomes evident is that equipped with
evolution-evolved mirror neurons, interdividual man cannot help being social,
even in his striving to avoid seemingly negative evolution-built-in mechanisms.
Now on top of the layers of the brain evolved earlier in
evolution – the reptilian, then the limbic or emotional brain – there is the cerebrum where most mirror neurons seem to be located, apparently in both the left
and right hemisphere of the brain. When triggered they in turn link with and
activate other neurons and systems, many of them located in those older parts
of the brain. And that may result in atavistic behavior that moral man would
not necessarily be proud of.
I assume here that in not so distant a future
neuroscience will be able to flesh out the bicamerality of the human brain. And
so while referring to existing studies, I allow myself now to speculate based
on this assumption. What follows then is my take on what plausibly happens in
the two approaches: the Buddhist and non-Buddhist,
including the Christian Christ-mimesis.
There are studies (referred to by, e.g., Daniel Siegel
and Iain McGilchrist) that indicate that the phenomenon of empathy involves mostly
mirror neurons located in the right brain, which is long known as holistic and
creative, as opposed to the left brain’s analytic as well as routine-enabling
function. It is thus entirely plausible that when the initial empathy “degenerates”
into or is cross-wired with desire to imitate one’s fellow man what is involved
then is predominately left brain’s mirror neurons. This cross-wiring must
become even more pronounced with mimesis of, as Girard posits, envy-based
desire devolving into rivalry and especially when it becomes violent. Parts of
the "older" brain fired then are not the ones that would be fired with pure
empathy.
One thing seemingly being successfully dealt with when
one gets involved headlong in the mimetic cycle is the problem of suffering.
Any nascent experience of suffering can here be apparently overcome through a
stronger involvement in the cycle – more adrenaline flowing, a clearly set goal
of pursuit. No need to look at suffering at this initial stage. A logical
reflection that it might come later as an unfortunate result of this
involvement is pushed aside by an expectation of attaining to the goal, or made
entirely impossible in that hyped-up state.
Suffering aside, on the mimetic rollercoaster one is able
all the more easily to employ resources of the left hemisphere – its
verbalizing and justifying function, in the absence of empathy. Which amounts
to total blindness, not only emotional: one actually does not see one’s fellow
man; instead it is a construct without a face and lacking proportions or any
human qualities, gradually yet more and more quickly becoming reduced to the
status of pure obstacle. Envy has given way to resentment, then to hatred. Scapegoating
is possible given conducive social conditions.
Seemingly nothing new here. Yet the reflection or,
partly, speculation as to the role of the respective hemispheres and mirror
neurons is truly shedding new light. On top on any scientific explanation it is
also able to provide a new approach based on meaningful METAPHOR.
Now in a religious or spiritual approach to
self-transformation any such metaphor might be very helpful and for some people
outright crucial, as reinforcing beliefs held initially. Nay, transporting one
onto a higher spiritual plane, one consistent with those beliefs yet much
richer and more meaningful.
And so classical Buddhism-advocated insight meditation
that is expected to gain insight (or reinforce the held belief, as many
postulate) into man’s basic impermanence and substantial nonexistence, is
nevertheless expected to be supplemented by an attitude of loving-kindness
toward everybody and everything that comes within man’s purview during that
meditation, and, indeed, beyond it. While
it might at first seem illogical, it makes sense based on contemporary
knowledge of the brain, because it fosters right-brain holistic approach to
oneself and all else, as indicated above. Otherwise the meditator would open
himself to the instigations of his left
brain and would easily fall prey to a sinister mimetic cycle of desire.
So what
could be a response in those terms of contemplative Christians advocating imitatio Christi? And, on the
other hand, is it not essentially and practically love that is being stressed
by the Buddhists, those proverbial nihilists, as put down not only by Girard,
but also by St. John Paul II, among many other Christian heavy-weights? Is not
God in (or, of) Christianity – love?
As
unfortunate as those pronouncements are, we should nevertheless see and
appreciate what imitatio Christi imbuing
Christian contemplation implies in those same terms applied to Buddhist insight
meditation.
On the one hand, the contemplative is reaching for an
abundance beyond compare, so any danger of the spiritual process devolving into
a vicious scarcity-fed mimetic cycle is nullified, or at least reduced to a
minimum. (That might happen when imitation instead of focusing on Christ, is
centered on the teacher or guide; the same danger lurks for guru-imitating
Buddhists, though.)
On the other hand, the only way to actually imitate
Christ in contemplation is quickly found out to consist in emptying oneself of
any “self” one may have constructed as a vehicle of contemplation, or virtuous
living, for that matter. In undergoing Christ-like kenosis spurred on only by
love of and for Christ, which two facets are in due course intuited as the same thing, the love that must of
necessity embrace one’s fellow humans, including one’s enemies, as well as the
whole universe.
In my opinion it is helpful to hold in one’s quest for
Christian contemplation onto the guiding metaphor of no-self, which actually is
“shorthand” for “kenosis unto nothing but Christ in place of self.” And just as
Christ’s kenosis is for eternity imbued with forgiveness and love, so is one to
hope will in due course be the case with one’s contemplation; the whole
transformative process duly grounded in faith.
Is it all that different from Buddhist insight-loving-kindness
meditation? Allowed by brain plasticity, in both cases the mimetic cross-wiring
has to be undone so that man can be emptied of his many a time culturally reinforced
at least if not acquired mimetic mechanisms. Man is actually shorn of self in
the process. Any guiding metaphor of self in this approach other than no-self would
just be standing in the way of nearing this ever elusive target. By the way, the
respective belief systems remain, resulting in the outcome being described in
differing terms. But that must not be viewed as a real obstacle to mutual
understanding, respect and kindness.
Now, what about Girard? Why did he choose not to delve
into this seemingly illuminative approach and insights to problems he investigated?
Only distaste for the apparent nihilism? He actually alluded at least once that
he himself was “very mimetic,” so he may have not wanted to investigate an approach apparently denying any utility to mimesis instead of trying to transform it.
Yet had he done so, he would have found that Buddhist
approach not only can be viewed as having started with an “innocent
self-sacrificing scapegoat” to reveal the scapegoat mechanism for what it was,
but also was arguably much less productive of scapegoats during its more than
slightly longer history, as compared to Christianity.
That “innocent self-sacrificing scapegoat” was (is) man
sacrificing his “self” instead of pumping it up to the point of creating
mimetic rivalry and conflict resulting in violence and the scapegoat, as has
been the case with the Christian and now post-Christian world. Such sacrifice is
actually hardly more than metaphoric or psychological. Stressing and employing non-sacrificial and
nonviolent means of pursuing peace has always been of utmost significance. And
those monks who chose to protest against injustice or “imperialist” incursion
by self-immolation made sure that it was nonviolent to anybody else, while also trying to maintain
equanimity of mind and heart that would shield them from any resentment or hatred
they might be feeling toward their perceived oppressors (Vietnam), while public peace
meditation gatherings manage to rally
tens of thousands of people in the public square (Thailand). Buddhism has always
been totally anti-sacrificial, to the point that some purists had insisted on
refraining from cooking due to its alleged association with sacrifice. And if
Buddhism is considered other-worldly or “atomistic,” one had better look again:
beggar-monk communities are willingly supported by communities at large, while in
turn receiving spiritual advice and guidance from the monks (Sri Lanka, Thailand).
Now Buddhism as a political force came into being with
Ashoka, a III century BCE Indian emperor who converted to that religion having
waged a bloody war of conquest, crushed by the inflicted suffering. While spreading
Buddhism and its dharma he subsequently managed to introduce peace and rule of law as well as social and even
animal welfare programs (he banned Vedic animal sacrifices) to his unified
empire. He had many pillars erected
across his empire, inscribed with his edicts meant also to spread Buddhist
dharma, with alphabetic writing being spread as well and Buddhist culture being
solidified.
Buddhism
in India fell on hard times especially in the wake of Islamic conquests as well
as resurging Hinduism, and virtually disappeared there by the XI century CE (though
some pockets survived much longer.) Yet not before it had spread to many adjacent
and far away countries which, leavened by its message, managed to evolve rich Buddhist
cultures of their own that managed to survive if not thrive as opposed to in its
cradle. And a revival Buddhist movement
in India started in the mid-1950s springing from a perception that Buddhism was
the only way for the Untouchables to escape their systemic scapegoating and to gain
equality.
Today many
Buddhist countries experience certain phenomena seemingly not in keeping with
their religious traditions. Colonialism has been blamed by some commentators as
having put its sinister stamp on them, while others ascribe their apparent lack
of vitality and social malaise precisely to Buddhism itself. It is true that in
some countries the situation looks (or just recently looked) rather bleak: Sri
Lanka is still licking wounds following a devastating civil war between the Buddhist
Sinhalese and Hinduist Tamils, while some Myanmar Buddhist monks are reported
to be leading the persecution of that
country’s Rohingya Moslem minority.
Those facts
and examples, which I gleaned mostly from countries of Theravada Buddhism (i.e.,
deriving from and based on its classical variety), are of course of interest to
historians, political scientists and religion comparatists but might or even
should be also to anthropologists, and especially so to those of a Girardian
bent. When combined with the seeming relevance and importance of Buddhist
religion and psychology to Girardian thought, Buddhism in all its aspects makes
all the more powerful a case for the need to be investigated from a mimetic theory
perspective. There might be significant
insights gained also for comparative social sciences when results of studies focusing
on a long-time ostensible societal devaluation, if not advocated suppression,
of mimetic desire are in.
No comments:
Post a Comment