Wednesday, July 27, 2022

Jose Ortega y Gasset on Love, with Thomas Aquinas (and Rene Girard) as a Foil

 

“Let us begin by talking about love, but not about "love affairs."” – so begins the Spanish philosopher Jose Ortega y Gasset’s introductory essay, “Features of Love” (Spanish title: Facciones del amor), contained in his On Love. Aspects of a Single Theme (Estudios sobre el amor). Arguably Rene Girard would have to disagree from the start, such an approach would smack to him of what he called romantic fallacy and which he so strongly opposed, to say the least, when analyzing human relationships. Yet the Spaniard clearly shows what both approaches, the “romantic” and the desire-based, entail, and leaves the reader free to decide whether the latter is capable of doing justice to the sentiment (his word) of love. His own answer is an unequivocal “no.” What he views as love, and sketches from a phenomenological perspective in the essay – largely via what it engenders or implies, Girard seems to leave entirely out of account.

Yet, as it is made clear in the essay, Girard’s approach could enlist the support of Thomas Aquinas thought in this respect. While not highlighting desire’s mimetic character, Aquinas nevertheless posits its preeminence in structuring man's orientation and actions in the world, and regards it as guiding man's relation to both good and evil, as well as governing his sentiments of love and hatred. Ortega y Gasset takes issue with Aquinas' approach to love, pointing out that desire-actuated love can only find consummation in appropriating its object, in effect in annihilating it finally. For Ortega y Gasset such an approach misses the point as to what true love is about, amounting as it does to an impoverishment of a most fecund, uplifting, if not ennobling sentiment.

When Ortega y Gasset criticizes Thomas of Aquinas’ view of love one realizes that, had he known Girard’s theory, he could as well have criticized it along the same lines:

“The idea of love that St. Thomas gives us, in summing up Greek tradition, is, obviously, erroneous. For him, love and hate are two forms of desire, appetite, or lust. Love is the desire for something good in so far as it is good — concupiscibile circa bonum; hate, a negative desire, a rejection of evil as such — concupiscibile circa malum. This reveals the confusion between appetites or desires and sentiments from which all psychology up to the eighteenth century suffered; a confusion which we again encounter in the Renaissance, though it is transferred to the realm of esthetics. Thus, Lorenzo the Magnificent says that I'amore e un appetito di bellezza.”…

“Nothing is so fertile in our private lives as the feeling of love; love even becomes the symbol of fertility. For many things are born out of a person's love: desire, thought, volition, action, All these things, however, which grow from love, like the harvest from a seed, are not love itself, but rather presuppose its existence. Of course, in some manner or form we also want what we love; but, on the other hand, we obviously want many things that we do not love, things which leave us indifferent on a sentimental plane. Desiring a good wine is not loving it, and the drug addict desires drugs at the same time that he hates them for their harmful effect.

“There is, however, another sounder and more subtle reason for distinguishing between love and desire. Desiring something is, without doubt, a move toward possession of that something ("possession" meaning that in some way or other the object should enter our orbit and become part of us). For this reason, desire automatically dies when it is fulfilled; it ends with satisfaction. Love, on the other hand, is eternally unsatisfied. Desire has a passive character; when I desire something, what I actually desire is that the object come to me. Being the center of gravity, I await things to fall down before me. Love… is the exact reverse of desire, for love is all activity. Instead of the object coming to me, it is I who go to the object and become part of it. In the act of love, the person goes out of himself. Love is perhaps the supreme activity which nature affords anyone for going out of himself toward something else. It does not gravitate toward me, but I toward it.

“St. Augustine, one of those who have thought about love most profoundly and who possessed perhaps one of the most gigantic erotic temperaments that ever existed, succeeds sometimes in freeing himself from the interpretation which makes of love a desire or appetite. Thus, he says with lyric expansiveness: Amor meus, pondus meum: illo feror, quocumque feror. "My love is my weight; where it goes I go." Love is a gravitation toward that which is loved.”…

“[I]n love we feel united with the object. What does this union mean? It is not merely physical union, or even closeness. Perhaps our friend (friendship must not be forgotten when love is generically considered) lives far away and we do not hear from him. Nevertheless, we are with him in a symbolic union — our soul seems to expand miraculously, to clear the distance, and no matter where he is, we feel that we are in essential communion with him.”…

“Love.. reaches out to the object… and is involved in an invisible but divine task, the most active kind that there is: it is involved in the affirmation of its object. Think of what it is to love art or your country: it consists of never doubting for an instant their right to exist; it is like recognizing and confirming at each moment that they are worthy of existence.”

“The reader will judge whether or not my analysis matches what he finds within himself.” – says Ortega y Gasset. Many if not most of us will say, “yes, it largely matches my (past) experience.” Of course those very same people would certainly recognize themselves in Girard’s descriptions of mimetic desire, including those that bear on intense romantic feelings. Could the relevant accounts, as contained, e.g., in Deceit, Desire and the Novel, or in A Theater of Envy, however, be called accounts of love as it is elucidated by Ortega y Gasset from what he himself implies to be a phenomenological perspective?

The Girardian mimetic desire-based love not only cannot be spontaneous – it is mimetically instigated – but it “automatically dies when it is fulfilled; it ends with satisfaction,” to repeat Ortega’s description of desire, which he recognizes as intrinsically acquisitive. Unless, says Girard, there appears a mediator to revivify it. But is that all that there is to it?

Mimetic theory can’t help but evince some of the same problems when it is brought to bear on love of God. But that is also where Girard came closest to making a normative case for imitation, namely for loving imitation of Jesus as the model of nonviolence par excellence. Now according to mimetic theory the Christian’s love of Jesus cannot but be imitation of someone else’s love of Jesus, which in turn is their imitation of someone else’s love of Jesus, etc., which imitation is ultimately supposed to lead to and consist in imitating Jesus’ love of the Father. But again, is that all that there is to it? And what about the acquisitive aspect of mimesis? Mimetic theory fails to factor it in as regards the imitative love of God; although Jesus is regarded as an external mediator, the same cannot be really expected of all those whose love of Jesus Christians are supposed to imitate, even if they tried to pick and choose their mediators. Is the implied endless chain of imitation supposed to be capable – if it is not a case of circular argument – of nullifying the curse of possessiveness, or deflecting it somehow, that otherwise would have to mean that this love, actuated as it is by someone else’s desire, “dies when it is fulfilled; it ends with satisfaction” (whatever it may mean with respect to a thusly mediated deity)? “Love, on the other hand, is eternally unsatisfied,” says Ortega y Gasset. Are we really misguided when we want to say amen to that?  

Monday, March 22, 2021

Jesus the Egalitarian

Against the backdrop of the Biblical notion of man created in Imago Dei, Jesus preaches radical, spiritual as well as this-worldly, equality from the vantage point of the humble, the persecuted and the powerless. This is effected by an authoritative reinterpretation of the Scriptures that he insists reflects their deep true spiritual meaning. Presenting himself as at once poor yet exceedingly well versed in Scripture, Jesus steps into the traditional prophetic pattern, and takes on the religious establishment of his country, the most important stratum of Jewish society, if not also the most powerful, given the Jews’ subjugation to Rome.

He has not one word of approval for what the religious hierarchy does or stands for, in fact accuses them of the worst transgressions imaginable, including of killing all prophets before him. Only long deceased religious leaders and dead prophets are exalted by him. Of the living he has this to say: “among those born of women there has not arisen anyone greater than John the Baptist! Yet the one who is least in the kingdom of heaven is greater than he,” a statement that Jesus’ followers (those who “have ears to hear”) might rightly interpret as egalitarian in its far-reaching consequences. In the context of his teaching on repentance it also shows the way for potential equality to become actual, which, paradoxically, for those who in society “are first” would involve their moving back – or else being moved – to “be last” (while “the last” would become “first”). What a way to introduce an equality principle!

All of this is grounded upon the foundational to Jesus’ ministry message contained in the Sermon of the Mount, with its exaltation of the downtrodden. They are called “the salt of the earth,” while the meek among them “shall inherit the earth.” Many blessings and rewards will be showered on them in the hereafter, and they seemingly will be reserved only for them. But that is not all that is to this message: those who are meek, or rather cannot but be meek in order to survive, while subsisting in this world are – as Walter Wink beautifully has shown – in fact instructed in tactics, perhaps a full-blown strategy for the discerning, of using existing cultural norms to shame their oppressors into mending their ways. Even the most famous one in this category, “whoever slaps you on your right cheek, turn the other to him also,” can be interpreted that way. But one is not supposed to hate his oppressor: “love your enemies and pray for those who persecute you, so that you may be sons of your Father who is in heaven; for He causes His sun to rise on the evil and the good, and sends rain on the righteous and the unrighteous.” Thusly understood and enjoined perfection, “as your heavenly Father is perfect,” is the other side of man’s radical equality in the sight of God.

But those societal as well as soteriological considerations are not all that he has to say in terms of equality advancement. The family also comes within Jesus’ purview in a way that is far from even resembling a traditional endorsement of it. The young man who wished to do his filial duty and bury his father was told, “Let the dead bury their dead,” hardly supportive of the patriarchal family’s ways. Also, when “Someone said to Him, “Behold, Your mother and Your brothers are standing outside seeking to speak to You.” …Jesus answered… “Who is My mother and who are My brothers?” And stretching out His hand toward His disciples, He said, “Behold My mother and My brothers! For whoever does the will of My Father who is in heaven, he is My brother and sister and mother.” This statement possibly goes even further, effectively replacing family with an earthly brother-(and sister-)hood of equals, provided they do the will of the heavenly Father.

It all culminates in the following: “Do not think that I came to bring peace on the earth; I did not come to bring peace, but a sword. For I came to set a man against his father, and a daughter against her mother, and a daughter-in-law against her mother-in-law; and a man’s enemies will be the members of his household.”

Whether this is a normative or just a descriptive statement makes little difference. Jesus shows that he knows perfectly well what consequences his message is bringing – but does not hesitate to introduce it anyway, as is done here in the framework of the family. He is “Girardian” before Girard has ever introduced his mimetic theory that warns of dangers of undifferentiation or radical equality. Regardless, the traditional patriarchal family, a bulwark against dangers of rivalry, conflict and, eventually, violence, apparently has to give way to such a one where nothing but God himself is sacred.

The Gospels are a treasure trove of spiritual inspiration. It is true that each new generation finds new themes, or sees other ones in a different light. For Christian gays and lesbians such is now the case with Luke 17:34-35: “…on that night there will be two men in one bed; one will be taken and the other will be left. There will be two women grinding together [“grind” is said to refer to sexual intercourse in at least four places in the Hebrew Bible]; one will be taken and the other will be left,” spoken by Jesus in the context of rapture. It is interpreted as signifying that sexually active gays and lesbians are not automatically consigned to eternal damnation on that basis alone, and further as bringing equality of human sexual expression.

Though equality of all humans may be derived from Imago Dei, Jesus’ message of equality, and not only in the sight of God, was addressed largely to Israel and specifically to the first communities of his Jewish disciples and followers. Paul went further, extending the message of equality beyond ethnic boundaries, making it universal in scope. What was yet implicit in Jesus became explicit in Paul, in his pronouncements concerning the standing before God of all the believers: “For all of you who were baptized into Christ have clothed yourselves with Christ. There is neither Jew nor Greek, there is neither slave nor free man, there is neither male nor female; for you are all one in Christ Jesus,” and “… [in] a renewal… there is no distinction between Greek and Jew, circumcised and uncircumcised, barbarian, Scythian, slave and freeman, but Christ is all, and in all.” Paul’s push to make Christianity a universal religion made the message of equality subversive also of societal hierarchies beyond Israel. Consequently, it was treated as public menace by the Roman Empire.

Monday, September 7, 2020

Demagoguery in Contemporary Democracy in Light of Mimetic Theory

Mimetic theory’s insistence on seeing man as a creature lacking autonomy and free will, as well as being basically a prey to his mimetically determined desires, has important implications for its analyses of the contemporary political arena. It results in a one-sidedness where the dynamics of mimetic desire therein are analyzed almost exclusively from the standpoint of a mob participant, or with a narrow focus on the mob as such. Political leadership barely enters the picture. There seems to be no scope given to political demagoguery, relying as it does on one-directional hypnotic suggestion on the part of the demagogue vis-à-vis his followers, and arguably amenable to analysis as a species of reverse external mediation of desire; nor has it been given to loving mimesis, potentially capable of introducing a new benevolent dynamic into politics, albeit on a smaller scale and more slowly than demagoguery – being as it is an intimate “conferral of imitation,” and amenable to analysis as a species of reverse internal mediation of desire. Yet when a spirit of loving mimesis has been able to flourish in the public arena its accomplishments have clearly been encouraging if not inspirational.

From a Girardian perspective, however, where every human motivation and action has precedence in mimetic desire, both the political demagogue and the loving mimeticist need also to be seen with a view to particular mechanisms of mimetic desire that actuate them. In broad strokes, the demagogue seems to be actuated first and foremost by way of internal mediation of his political rivals’ desires, perceived as envious and ressentiment-filled, as they play out in the public arena (while his followers largely by that of his rivals’ followers), on top of more than just a kick-starter of external mediation of some “worthy” exemplars of political demagoguery, be they contemporary foreigners or historical figures; whereas the loving mimeticist is actuated by way of external mediation of a benevolent model’s perceived or imagined desires and motivation as reflected in his/her actions, preserved sayings and other written records.

The present essay attempts to see the mimetic triangle as introduced and elaborated by Rene Girard first and foremost as being about relative power in relationships, about dynamic distribution thereof. Being a commonplace in the political arena, the mimetic triangle is predominately about gaining or maintaining power on a mass scale using its dynamics. And when a demagogue enters the political scene, sooner rather than later, if not from the very beginning, it is exclusively about power, about cornering power therein. Demagogues are naturals at exploiting mimetic power dynamics to their advantage. Plus, if mimetic theory has any clue, their armamentarium is vastly superior to that of a benevolent leader, especially one inspired by Christianity: unlike the latter they can fall back on and exploit to their advantage the scapegoat mechanism. In fact, one doesn’t have to be mimetic theory-literate to appreciate its potential in political struggle. Recent neuroscientific research suggests that dominant people’s brains entrain those of submissive people as they synchronize while interacting. It follows that a masterly demagogue might be able to effect that via social or mass media.  

 xxx

Contemporary liberal democracy arguably increasingly ceases to be “liberal,” unless that designation is limited to signify just one, currently predominant, neoliberal variety. But in caring only to safeguard at all costs what neoliberalism stands for first and foremost, i.e., a global (ostensibly) free market, contemporary liberal democracy tends to produce an inequality that must be glossed over by political demagogues foisting themselves on top of an electorate divided on whatever basis that would work for them – other than wealth and true privilege. Then from their vantage positions at the top they would have one part of the under- or less-privileged set upon the other, with them leading the fray on both sides. In the process liberal democracy also tends to shed its plurality, apparently hardly caring any more about many of its recent constitutive elements, such as mutual respect and tolerance as shared values that underlie any conception of the common good therein. It is reflected in and/or driven by a gradual diminishment of the intended role of its institutional checks and balances, or worse yet, their blatant enlistment in partisan politics. Without their sufficient countervailing influence liberal democracy tends to devolve into “pure” democracy, such as greatest philosophers, starting with Plato, were sternly warning against. Given the current starting point of that process – the greatest centralization of state power that history has ever known, concurrent globalization processes as a backdrop notwithstanding – demagogues that this devolution tends to produce at an ever faster rate are given opportunities to get hold of more power than ever has been possible to date. Naturally they use it to undermine the remaining bases of plurality in society, or do away with them altogether. Also, their squashing or abusing of systems of checks and balances in the name of “people” democracy goes hand in hand with an ever increasing centralization of the state, a process that will not be completed until they are in a position to do away with the democracy itself.

What currently thwarts their efforts and gives them pause is a phenomenon that canonical mimetic theory seems unable to explain if not is totally oblivious to, viz., an ever deepening polarization splitting society almost exactly in half on any issue of consequence – instead of polarizing it against a single person or group, i.e., a scapegoat, in an unwitting push to obtain societal peace at its expense. It can perhaps be explained, however, in terms of pure power dynamics: in place of liberal democracy’s ever weakening systems of checks and balances and the concomitant lack of public trust what seems to be maintaining a semblance of societal peace is a power equilibrium, inherently unstable though it is, that is holding for the time being, an equilibrium resulting from an almost equal power apparently mustered by both inimical sides – their relative powers determined by their almost equal sizes, both sides’ constant reconstituting notwithstanding. In fact if and when the precarious balance is tipped to the advantage of a demagogue-led illiberal movement liberal democracy’s days will be numbered – as currently seems to be the case with Hungary.

xxx

Now the political demagogue’s malevolent actions should best be seen as deliberate manipulations, especially his use of scapegoating of whole populations – his main tool, even if much of his dealings in the public arena with his counterparts, i.e., demagogues on the other end of the political spectrum, may be in the mold of internal mediation of desire, and thus mostly unwitting. How then can mimetic theory, a theory that focuses chiefly on the randomness of scapegoating and imitation, that analyzes the mimetic process predominantly from the standpoint of the passive or unwitting imitator lacking personal autonomy, be of any help when scrutinizing demagoguery and its appeal? Well, there is a body of work by Jean-Michel Oughourlian that contains valuable insights concerning the role of hypnotic suggestion in mimesis as seen within the context of mimetic theory. They may be able to shed light on the processes inherent in the malevolent use of hypnotic suggestion and hypnotic induction in a mimetic power relationship when one of its sides deliberately sets out to influence the other. In order to appreciate their unfolding in the political arena one would do well to glean and combine relevant insights especially from his two books, Psychopolitics and The Mimetic Brain.

In short: political demagogues are adept at introducing power into public mimetic relationships – in order to manipulate them. Instead of being about the unwitting imitation of a model (external mimesis) or rival (internal mimesis; which, however, can also be the basis of loving mimesis) on the part of the imitator acting in the political arena, mimesis then reverses direction and becomes one about suggestion first and foremost (although the manipulator also feeds on his followers’ adulation that he has managed to generate in the first place), a suggestion foisted on “a crowd with only two members” (Freud) who in that arena multiply into a malleable mass. In the contemporary West its members either resist him as rival (the case of those who oppose the demagogue for reasons often scarcely recognized or acknowledged, yet somehow reflective – though often seemingly randomly – of their various personal narratives and social circumstances; very few of his opponents are able to simply reject or dismiss him – and then be mostly indifferent to him – rather than resisting him in a mimetic fashion, as their antimodel, whether or not having first recognized their desires’ alterity – antithetical as it is to his – and him as their locus, and staying adversatively involved with him); or imitate him as model (his followers).“[W]hat leads to the abandonment of freedom and to dependency is the ‘need for direction,’ that is to say the path of least resistance for mimetic desire, which delegates the choice not of a single object but of all its objects to a single, absolute model,” says Oughourlian with regard to model imitation from the perspective of the follower. Based on an initial single-issue attraction, she or he then is led to follow unreflectively the demagogue’s whole agenda, while his opponents do the same in reverse: repulsed perhaps by his (demagogical in their eyes) stance on a single issue of importance to them, the dynamic leads them not so much to simply reject his whole agenda as to resist it in a mimetic fashion – for the duration, until in fact their resentment is trumped by that toward another, suddenly more worthy subject. If unchecked somehow, the process as envisioned here tends to be self-feeding and evidently ever more polarizing. Additionally, it is easy to see from the above (and the likes of James Madison and Edmund Burke saw it clearly) that the so called mob rule never is what it is purported to be: its agenda is manipulatively foisted on them by a ruthless demagogue rather than somehow decided in a “purely” democratic process. It is he rather than the mob by themselves that insinuates into the process the scapegoat mechanism, in order to solidify their nascent uniformity and support for him.

xxx

In the face of political power apparently being accumulated and distributed via constantly reconfigured mimetic triangles that tend to encompass ever widening circles of people – what actually can be done? How to counteract the inordinate accumulation of power by unscrupulous political demagogues who consciously or unwittingly use or instinctively fall back on every trick imaginable from the armamentarium of mimetic theory to create and hold mimetic mobs in their thrall? It is a hard goal to accomplish, not least because it would be very difficult to effect a socially and psychologically acceptable equilibrium in a situation marked by such strong mimetic dynamics.

Yet every step of the process of the current devolution of liberal democracy described above can be elucidated with the help of mimetic theory (some of it perhaps uncanonical), something that has hardly been done in any systematic way so far, as well as measures proposed that might be used in attempts to thwart its sinister unfolding. Arguably, the theory’s most needful use would be elucidation of anything having to do with the rise to power of demagogues in a contemporary liberal democracy that undergoes such convulsions. Moreover, there is a possibility to elaborate a positive scenario here, viz., that of fostering the emergence of benevolent leaders, such as would be ready for self-sacrifice themselves. The latter characteristic is the only element of this whole process tangentially touched upon by Girard – when on occasion he would mention, almost in passing, the need to imitate Jesus or those who imitate him.

What at a minimum needs to be done is to field or support political leaders who would embrace an agenda prominently featuring fostering a climate of societal tolerance (while, on the downside, curbing hate speech in social media) and trust, as well as promoting political and social pluralism and diversity (including in the field of economic activity). But in view of the theory’s focus on the dangerous dynamics of internal mediation inherent in excessive societal uniformity mimetic theory could also be put to use to shed light on changes to the institutional shape of liberal democracy that need to be implemented to prevent giving free rein to demagogues in those circumstances (though the theory’s concentration, limited and reactionary, is on dangers having to do with abolishing social hierarchies): polarizing mimetic dynamics attendant upon the workings of demagogues would have to be seen for what they are and effectively circumscribed in scope as well as sapped of as much of its harmful energy as possible. To effect a societal reconfiguration that would successfully embody those insights, adopted measures would arguably have to include institutionalizing and safeguarding a decentralization of the state that would make extensive use of the principle of subsidiarity; possibly employing a principle of supermajority in referendums ratifying major or radical changes, such as constitutional reforms or gaining national independence; as well as introducing greater reliance on a participatory democracy that would be guided by a consensus-seeking spirit, especially at the local level, with a view to promoting egalitarian communitarianism and cooperation based on people’s affinities of interests and values.

Q & A

Q: My understanding is that Girard claims that Jesus broke Satan's snare and as a result scapegoating has lost its efficacy. Doesn't that explain why we polarize into factions that oppose each other instead of restoring peace via an eternal return to mythical, single-victim ritual sacrifice? Doesn't his theory predict that without a complete renunciation of violence we are left with ever escalating conflict in human affairs?

A: Yes, it does. Yet, as mentioned above, the present take is a bit noncanonical as far as mimetic theory goes, in the sense that Girard did not seem to have predicted or perhaps even considered as highly probable that “scapegoating losing its efficacy” should in fact in liberal democracy take the route of splitting society in half. I argue that otherwise demagogues would still be able to polarize it against a single person or group, i.e., a scapegoat – in a way that would be “efficacious.”

Not that societal sacrifice doesn’t happen anymore, it does in a major way, through economic exclusion, etc.; it is often invisible to society, as we all know. But there is no unity and peace around that sacrifice, it doesn’t make for a unified society, it is not celebrated any more by the whole society. And if a demagogue chooses scapegoating as a way of gaining support, his “officiating” at an exclusionary ritual is vigorously opposed by half of it.

The point is that this splitting in half that accompanies polarization is what guarantees that “efficaciousness” does not return. If, however, one of the sides begins to become relatively stronger, a dynamic sets in whereby in the long run the demagogue controlling it is able to make sure that the other side is cowed into submission, and perhaps eventually disintegrates. Bending or breaking the rules of liberal democracy is how the demagogue’s support is then solidified – to make sure that the other side cannot regain its lost strength/numbers, that nothing is standing in the way of scapegoating and public sacrificial rituals returning as his tools of choice. Democracy becomes nothing more than a façade. That is what is happening right now in Hungary. And of course all of that is a long way from our renouncing violence altogether.